J. P. Guilford « POETICKS

Archive for the ‘J. P. Guilford’ Category

Entry 1372 — My Psychology & Guilford’s

Saturday, February 15th, 2014

Today I’ll try to make sense about Guilford’s theory of intelligence versus mine.

Guilford’s Structure of Intellect

According to Guilford’s Structure of Intellect (SI) theory (1955), an individual’s performance on intelligence tests can be traced back to the underlying mental abilities or factors of intelligence. SI theory comprises up to 150 different intellectual abilities organized along three dimensions—Operations, Content, and Products.

My theory of cerebreffectiveness, which is more or less what Guilford’s “intellect” is, also posits numerous different intellectual abilities along with what might be called three dimensions: my charactration (unless I changed its name),  accommodance and accelerance.  Are they much like Guilford’s operations, content and products?  One way they definitely are not is that my three have a single mechanism over them which I consider the g factor (which he considered his theory to reject, although I don’t think it does).

It is a mechanism I call the “cerebrexecutive” which is responsible for supervising the interaction of the three cerebral dimensions responsible for all we think and do.  To describe the process simply, the cerebrexecutive oversees the flow of cerebral energy; that determines the way the three . . . “subcerebrexecutives” interact, which in turn determines which master-cells will be activated to produce the thoughts and behavior of the individual involved at that time.  Said master-cells contribute to many operations, perhaps the same ones  Guilford hypothesized, or ones similar to them.  They are the final determinants of cerebreffectiveness.

Note: I hope to get a decent name for my three operations.  Maybe “cerebreffectors.”  Or “cerebranisms.”

Eventually, I hope to provide detailed examples of thinking and behavior that will make all this much more clear than I suspect my previous paragraph does.

Operations dimension

SI includes six operations or general intellectual processes:

  1. Cognition – The ability to understand, comprehend, discover, and become aware of information.
  2. Memory recording – The ability to encode information.
  3. Memory retention – The ability to recall information.
  4. Divergent production – The ability to generate multiple solutions to a problem; creativity.
  5. Convergent production – The ability to deduce a single solution to a problem; rule-following or problem-solving.
  6. Evaluation – The ability to judge whether or not information is accurate, consistent, or valid.

Interesting.  It seems to me my theory treats cognition, memory recording and memory retention as a single process.  For me, sensory-cells are activated by stimuli in both the external and internal environments and, in turn activate master-cells (m-cells) in the cerebrum.  This activation the individual involved experiences as perceptual information.   At the same time, certain master-cells are activated whose activation the individual experiences as “retroceptual” information (or memories).  In other words, the individual becomes aware of a given moment’s information both from the immediate environments and recalled while data is recorded.

Note: I have no explanation for the individual’s consciousness of perceived and remember data.  That the individual exists with a consciousness that acts as I describe is the ground premise of my theory.  All I can say about it is that it exists.  (If it doesn’t exist, then I call what it does do as existing.)

At the same time that the individual becomes aware of what he perceives and remembers, he automatically forms a preliminary understanding, comprehension, discovery, idea, etc., of it.  Example: When little Willie sees a black cat, his nervous system activates m-cells whose activation he understands to mean “black cat.”  His nervous system also activates m-cells whose state he understands as “Max,” the name the actual cat reminds him is its.  We could call the three fused processes “cognition,” it seems to me.  Large forms of cognition, of course, occur; they simply take longer to do so, and include chains of moments rather than a single one.  Little Willie, watching his cat, connects it to the cockroach he saw scampering across the floor a moment ago (I’m drawing on my sad experience as an impoverished super-genius here–please send me some money) and may form an enlarged understanding of the situation.

Guilford’s other three operations are more complex.  Divergent production is what happens, according to my theory, when the cerebrexecutive puts the accommodance mechanism in charge of things.  What that does I will describe elsewhere.  Here, it suffices to say, it is the brain’s way of being creative.  (It causes the brain to become disorganized enough to form the novel linkages of data that creativity requires, to put it most simply.)

As for convergent production, that occurs, according to my theory, when the cerebrexecutive puts the charactration mechanism in charge (or, more exactly, leaves it in charge since it’s the cerebrum’s default boss).  This causes the narrowed concentration needed to follow a possible solution to a problem to its conclusion.  Accelerance will generally participate in both operations.  In divergence, it helps the brain pull quickly pull in a potential solution once recognized.  In convergence it strengthens and narrows the focus to defeat distraction until the solution is arrived at.

As for “evaluation,” I consider that a part of both divergent and convergent thinking.  If one’s cerebrexecutive is a good one, it will bring accelerance and accommodance into play in such a way as judge each attempted solution to a problem.

In short, it seems to me, that my theory contains all the operations Guilford’s does, although with much different mechanisms responsible for them–and, I suspect, with their nature, interactions and effects much more deeply worked out.

Content dimension

SI includes four broad areas of information to which the human intellect applies the six operations:

  1. Figural – Concrete, real world information, tangible objects — things in the environment. It includes visual: information perceived through seeing; auditory: information perceived through hearing; and kinesthetic: information perceived through one’s own physical actions.
  2. Symbolic – Information perceived as symbols or signs that stand for something else, e.g., Arabic numerals, the letters of an alphabet, or musical and scientific notations.
  3. Semantic – Concerned with verbal meaning and ideas. Generally considered to be abstract in nature.
  4. Behavioral – Information perceived as acts of people. (This dimension was not fully researched in Guilford’s project, remains theoretical, and is generally not included in the final model that he proposed for describing human intelligence.)

Guilford’s  “content” translates readily into my theory of awarenesses.  His “figural” is the same as the content of my fundaceptual awareness, which is where all our fundamental perceptions of our inner and outer environments are recorded as they occur or are remembered.  His “symbolic” content is the content of my reducticeptual awareness.  His semantic content is in this awareness, too–in the verboceptual subawareness of the reducticeptual awareness–since it is also symbolic.  It is, in fact, a dominant region of that awareness.  Guilford’s behavioral dimension is not researched at all in my project but is definitely part of it.  But it supplies the content of an awareness with much else in it, the anthroceptual awareness, which has to do with all human acts, our own as well as those of others, and the acts of all living creatures as well (and supernatural ones, too!)

My theory also has a behavraceptual awareness, but its function is to carry out our own behavior.  Like all the awarenesses, it interacts with other awarenesses, so contributes to the anthroceptual awareness to possibly help it do some of the things one’s behavioral dimension does.  My theory covers many more kinds of content than Guilford’s does, for it has, at last count, ten major awarenesses, most of them with many sub-awarenesses.  These I will introduce later.

Product dimension

As the name suggests, this dimension contains results of applying particular operations to specific contents. The SI model includes six products, in increasing complexity:

  1. Units – Single items of knowledge.
  2. Classes – Sets of units sharing common attributes.
  3. Relations – Units linked as opposites or in associations, sequences, or analogies.
  4. Systems – Multiple relations interrelated to comprise structures or networks.
  5. Transformations – Changes, perspectives, conversions, or mutations to knowledge.
  6. Implications – Predictions, inferences, consequences, or anticipations of knowledge.

Therefore, according to Guilford there are 5 x 3 x 6 = 90 intellectual abilities or factors (his research only confirmed about three behavioral abilities, so it is generally not included in the model). Each ability stands for a particular operation in a particular content area and results in a specific product, such as Comprehension of Figural Units or Evaluation of Semantic Implications.

I’m not entirely sure just how parallel my theory is to Guilford’s idea of products.  His units suggest my knowlecules, or units of data concerning one stimulus or stimulus cluster the individual takes as a unified whole (or not, depending on the context–e.g., a horse is such a unified whole, but so is a horse’s mane, or a herd of horses.  His classes are like what I call “knowleplexes”–for data more complicated than single units, like the entire field of zoology.  I consider his other products as simply different combinations of knowlecules.

I believe my theory contains elements his does not.  I’m thinking of mechanisms for determining cerebral pain and pleasure, which contribute greatly to cerebreffectiveness.  It’s what tags thoughts as errors or acts of a Grumman.  I mean, of genius.  Also the etiologiplex (or whatever I’m calling it) which is responsible for apprehending a thing’s cause or effect and recording it, which is obviously important cerebreffectively.  Ah, and there are many instincts in my theory such as fear of snakes, recognition of human faces, vicarious sympathy, etc., that could be considered products like Guilford’s.  A set of innate personae like Jung’s, too.

Guilford’s original model was composed of 120 components (when the behavioral component is included) because he had not separated Figural Content into separate Auditory and Visual contents, nor had he separated Memory into Memory Recording and Memory Retention. When he separated Figural into Auditory and Visual contents, his model increased to 5 x 5 x 6 = 150 categories. When Guilford separated the Memory functions, his model finally increased to 180 factors.

I suspect if I carried out the same calculation with my equivalents of Guilford’s operations, content and products, I’d get a lot more categories than 150.  I think I’d have at least one more set of factors, too–at the tail end of each sequence when muscles or glands turn a cerebreffect (i.e., the final result of a cerebrexecutive command) into an action (which isn’t always the case because many sequences end in thoughts or feeling only).  At this tail end, purely physical abilities convert the cerebreffective portion of the sequence into anthreffectiveness, the success of which can be due in great part to the effectiveness of the muscles’ or glands’ contribution.  But here my concern is only with Guilford’s idea of intelligence, or intellectual ability, and mine of cerebreffectiveness.

Criticism

Various researchers have criticized the statistical techniques used by Guilford. According to Jensen (1998), Guilford’s contention that a g-factor was untenable was influenced by his observation that cognitive tests of U.S. Air Force personnel did not show correlations significantly different from zero. According to one reanalysis, this resulted from artifacts and methodological errors. Applying more robust methodologies, the correlations in Guilford’s data sets are positive.  In another reanalysis, randomly generated models were found to be as well supported as Guilford’s own theory.

My criticism is merely that Guilford never had a chance to discuss his theory with me.  I think mine does what he was trying to do.  I doubt the application of statistics to his theory or competitors of it have much chance of being of value.  Too many variables concerned.

I’m pleased I got into Guilford.  His theory suggests to me that I’m not that much of a crank.  No doubt I’m finding it more like mine than it really is.  Still, I didn’t feel like I was straining too much to reveal the possible similarities I did.  Another plus of my adventure is that I think I learned a little more about what I’m doing.  Best of all, I had fun!  Zah-goo!

.

AmazingCounters.com

The Human Instincts « POETICKS

Archive for the ‘The Human Instincts’ Category

Entry 1328 — My Stupidest Idea?

Thursday, January 2nd, 2014

About a month ago I had an idea so stupid I never wrote it down.  But somehow I more than half believe in it!  In any case, it may be entertaining, and I need something for today, so here it is: when we struggle to answer some problem and fail, our brain will eventually connect it to–here’s my idea–a False Solution.  Here’s what makes it wacko: we know it’s false but accept it as our solution, anyway!  And it explains nothing, it just says to you, you got it without telling you why.

Here’s what I tentatively think happens: a mechanism recognizing great puzzlement sticks this false solution to our thinking about the problem, with it clearly labeled “crap”; but the mechanism also lowers the pain that failed solutions generally cause, and which make us keep struggling with the problems causing them.  So we accept it.  It keeps us from ever solving the problem BUT makes up for that by keeping us from wasting too much time and energy trying to solve a problem we can’t solve, because we’re too inept, or have no likelihood of acquiring sufficient data to solve it, or it’s unsolvable (e.g., why iz we here).

To cast a better light on it, I could call it the Unsolvability Urceptual Knowlecule (UUK).  A form of x is x because.

The alert amongst you may well see how such a thing may just explain . . . You-Know-Who, Almighty.  In fact, I think certain things some find animistic vague answers to may connect to the UUK, which strengthens and personifies them.  In other words, if it exists, it would be the basis of a human instinct to form and believe in religions.  Always in tension with the instinct to be rational, even–I suspect–for the most devout.  And, in reverse, for the least devout.
.

Entry 946 — Pronouncements & Blither, Part 7

Saturday, December 8th, 2012

This entry was to consist of two paragraphs I wrote yesterday in which I tried to get a start on something major about the definition of “definition”–as a first step toward my final attempt at definitive book on poetry.  Except that I soon realized my first step should be about names.  Anyway, according to my diary, I thought my efforts lame.  I still thought them worth posting here–but somehow they got deleted.  So, instead, the beginning of something I threw together earlier today after getting a yen to list all the major human instincts I could think of:

1. The Fundaceptual Awareness

None I can think of.

2. The Behavraceptual Awareness

None I can think of.

3. The Evaluceptual Awareness

The Pleasure-Seeking Instinct

The Pain-Avoidance Instinct

The Evaluative Instinct

4. The Cartoceptual Awareness

The Self-Location Instinct

5. The Objecticeptual Awareness

None I can think of.

6. The Reducticeptual Awareness

The Analytic Instinct

7. The Sagaceptual Awareness

The Reproductive Instinct

The Hunting Instinct

The Escape Instinct

The Heroic-Self Instinct

8. The Anthroceptual Awareness

The Love Instinct

The Friendship Instinct

The Maternal Instinct

The Hostility Instinct

The Dominance Instinct

The Servility Instinct

The Individualism Instinct?

The Collectivism Instinct?

9. The Scienceptual Awareness

The Cause and Effect Instinct

10. The Combiceptual Awareness

None.

I’m trying to arrange them by which of my Knowlecular Psychology’s ten kinds of major awarenesses they belong in.  The list, of course, is almost entirely for me–to give me something to look at and think about.  It’s already given me ideas: the possibility of an instinct causing us to seek solitude and/or be different from others, and an opposite one to seek a herd to be part of and/or avoid being or seeming different occurred to me for the first time.

I know there are omissions, probably important ones.  But it’s a start.

.

Psychology « POETICKS

Archive for the ‘Psychology’ Category

Entry 1632 — Happiness/Unhappiness, Part 2

Saturday, November 15th, 2014

I guess I’m fully in my null zone now—beyond even the help of my hydrocodone pills.  Will return to the review I commented on yesterday, as promised, but only briefly—to take issue with another passage in it:

“Nor is it clear that if we were singling out just two positive feelings, we would choose pleasure and purpose.  Both of these are, of course, umbrella concepts, including moods and feelings with important qualitative differences; consider the pleasure of a good book, a swim in the ocean, a visit to Berlin, a conversation with a friend, or settling down for an afternoon nap.  Each of these might involve purpose as well.  And if the goal is to fasten on what matters most, there are many other possible umbrella candidates, including serenity, passion and commitment.  In the history of the world, only a small percentage of cultures would single out pleasure and purpose.  This does not mean that (singling them out) is wrong, but it does suggests that a sustained argument, not provided (in the books under review) would be necessary to justify the choice.

“But there is a more modest and less contentious version of (the idea of focusing on pleasure and purpose when pursuing happiness). It would put aside the deeper questions and urge that pleasure and purpose are important, and that many people’s lives have less pleasure and less meaning than they might, in part because of how they allocate their attention.  We need not take a stand of the most fundamental issues in order to agree that when people suffer, or feel that life lacks much of a point, one reason is where they choose to focus their attention–and that an appreciation of this point might help the reduce suffering and restore a sense of purpose.”

Okay, I more or less agree with Cass R. Sunstein, the author of the above, that pleasure and purpose can both be parts of an experience of happiness.  To expand on what I said yesterday, what I more exactly believe is that one will pursue purpose in the hopes of the happiness of attaining it.  Let me add that I believe healthy brains make the pursuit of a purpose (scoring a goal in a hockey game, for instance) pleasurable!

With regard to what Sunstein says, I would claim that he is discussing only one “umbrella concept, “Happiness,” or “the attainment of pleasure.”  “Serenity, passion and commitment” are just kinds of happiness.

I’ve already at various times this year bumbled through attempts to list the kinds of pleasure there are.  Any intelligent attempt to figure out how best to pursue a happy life should begin with such a list.  A second need is to recognize that everyone will have (1) a different list of pleasures (and pains) he is sensitive to, and a different level of sensitivity to each item on the list; (2) that context will be extremely important for determining how much a given pleasure or pain is for a particular person;*1 (3) that a person’s reports about the level of pain or pleasure he is experiencing is vastly less valuable than the neurophysiological measurement of it which I believe will be possible before too long, if it isn’t already: (4) that whether a given action will maximize one’s pleasure-to-pain ratio will almost always be in doubt—taking it a gamble; but that reason can help—i.e., knowing exactly what one is doing, how it worked in the past and how it seems to have worked for others; (5) that one should try to trace the possible effect of an action as far into the future as possible, and within every awareness; (6) a list like this will always seem puerile, because so common-sensical, except when not, and never anywhere near complete.

Which is my way of saying I’ve said enough on this topic for now.

*1 I’ve already forgotten what my general term for “feeling of either pleasure or pain” is.  I must have one!

.

AmazingCounters.com

Entry 1631 — Happiness/Unhappiness

Friday, November 14th, 2014

I cut the following out of the 4 December issue of The New York Review of Books because I wanted to cite the two books reviewed but didn’t feel like doing the necessary typing.  That’s me everywhere now-a-times.

Happiness^Unhappiness

The books sound semi-intelligent and the review seems intelligent and interesting, but my megalomania requires me to state that all three would be 7.6 times better had their authors consulted . . . ME.  Assuming I’d have the energy to answer them.

Note, I have to insert here that yesterday I played tennis in the seniors men’s league I’m in despite being 80% crippled, as far as I’m concerned: I can walk pretty well, but can’t run, unless being able to hobble a yard or two with vigor counts as running.  Just about everyone on my team was injured, so I had to play.  Ridiculously, our captain wanted me to play with him in first court–i.e., against our opponents best team!  I still can’t figure out how it happened, but we won.  So apparently I am capable of energy, when it counts!

Today being another off-day for me, although not one of my worst such days, I just want to deal with one passage from the review previously mentioned: “Many people insist that it matters if people help others, not because it makes them happy to help (it might not), but because the most important thing, or one the most important things, is helping others.”

I’m quoting this because it suggests that people consider other things more important than happiness–or what I would call “pleasure.”  They do not.  Take a person who hates mowing lawns but spends an hour mowing the lawn of a neighbor unable to do it himself and too poor to pay someone else to do it (whom he barely knows).   I say he mows the lawn not because doing a good deed is more important than happiness but (a) to avoid potential unhappiness and/or (b) to enjoy that old white man stand-by, deferred gratification.  In other words, he is motivated entirely to maximize his pleasure to pain ratio . . . in the long run.

Among the possibilities: it makes him happy to win the esteem of those who believe in helping others; it assures him that others who believe in helping others will not make him unhappy by looking down on him for failing to help someone in need.  Maybe he also thinks the exercise will do him good–keep him in good enough shape to enjoy the happiness of beating his brother in tennis, say.  Maybe he wants the good opinion of the neighborhood.

Clearly, he does want his life to have meaning, and believes helping others will provide it.  But that will make him happy.  Perhaps he can’t not have the anticipatory happiness of getting a gold star for helping others.

What it seems to me that those interested how best to achieve happiness should investigate is a given person’s knowleplex (large understanding) of “a meaningful life.”  I contend we instinctively seek to have such a life (most of us, at least)–because “meaning,” whatever it is, makes us happy, by giving us pleasure.  And I admit to feeling like a six-grader writing for fourth-graders for saying this.

More on this tomorrow.

.

AmazingCounters.com

Entry 1499 — Second-Level Drives

Sunday, June 29th, 2014

Today is a red-letter day for me: I finally finished a decent rough draft of the essay I’ve been working one most days for two months or so.  It began as an attempt to show how biologically beneficial an attraction to beauty, and therefore at, is.  It ended as around 4,500 words on what I’m calling the cerebral-satisfaction drive, which I elitistly oppose with the reptilian-satisfaction drive.  But they are opposites only in certain ways, although dramatic, profoundly important ways, the way men and women are opposites, but only in certain ways.  And, in the final analysis, equally important.

(Do spell-check programs ever know that words can end in “ly?”)

I left beauty completely out of the final version of my essay but will deal with it.  In fact, I now have 4,500 words of an essay on it in-progress–all cut from the essay on cerebral satisfaction.  Besides changing my essay’s focus, I extremely simplified it, leaving out almost all the details.  I kept simplifying and simplifying.  I don’t think it’s an exaggeration to say the present version is six layers of simplification simpler than the initial version.  Believe it or not, I could simplify it even more!  But I hope it won’t need it.

It’s about the art and science drives, basically  I guess it could be considered about the metaphysics and theology drives, too.  Any drive significantly to know or make beyond what’s needed for survival.  I was hoping to write something for a wide-circulation culture magazine, a British internet magazine called Aeon being the particular one I was aiming for.  I’m not ready to submit it anywhere yet, though.  Nor am I as confident as I was when just beginning the essay that it would be submittable.  I’ll see how I feel after I’ve let it sit for a while.

Oh, my entry title is because I at first thought my cerebral- and reptilian-satisfaction drives were second-level drives under what I consider the main drive of sentient beings–certainly of human beings–the pleasure-maximization drive.  Then I realized  those two drives were under what I call the exploratory-drive.  The only other secondary drive I can think of would be the security-drive.  But I’ve only just considered the question.

.

AmazingCounters.com

Entry 1465 — My Latest Coinages!!!

Monday, May 26th, 2014

I more and more fear I am only able to think in words.  Well, I guess I think in visual images when working on visual poems.  And I suspect I use items larger than words in my deepest moments.  Still, the truth is, I can’t deal with namelessnesses.  That’s why I so often suffer attacks of neologicomania.

My latest coinages came up yesterday.  All I wanted for the essay I was working on was a quick-and-easy list of the currents a person’s stream of consciousness can have in it.  It’s now a wobbly half-baked formal-almost taxonomy of . . . cerebrahension, which is my term for all the ways our nervous system puts one’s experience of existence into what I call one’s cerebraflux, my goofy term for the stream of consciousness that I’m 90% sure I’ll drop.  Among the ways we cerebrahend are constrictahending, freehending and physprehending, for–roughly–goal-directed thinking, letting your mind wander, and keeping track of what your body is doing and occasionally directing it.  “Physprehending” was the first of these to occur to me–because I didn’t like “proprieceiving,” which was the only other term for it I could think of.  “Cerebrahending” seems okay to me, and I like “freehending.”  “Physprehending” I can stand.  I want something shorter than “constrictahending,” though.  “Direcrehending” was the best of my previous tries.

My final coinage of the day was MUHD luh hehn dihng.

.

AmazingCounters.com

Enter 1406 — Some Dippy Thoughts

Friday, March 28th, 2014

Maybe I should have given this entry the title, “Some Thoughts More Dippy Than Even Mine So Frequently Are.”  That would have run-over, probably twice, and I hate it when my titles need two or more lines.  I don’t know how to change the size of the type in my titles to get more of them on one line.  Anyway, here’s my first dippy thought:

That some people are too stupid to get Alzheimer’s.  (That’s not aut0biographical!)

Another is so dippy as to be Pretty Danged Interesting: it occurred to me while I was reflecting on the many very nice girls I knew in high school, some of whom I now think might have made my life a lot better had I married them.  Actually, it’s what I believe must be a totally original reason for not getting married, one of the major questions I not infrequently ask myself.  My new partial answer is that I have such a remarkable ability to learn that I completely learn (and feel) everything a woman could give me for a lifetime in a few classes shared with her during three years of high school.  Applied to why I’ve been much less sexually active during my life than most healthy men, it means I can remember each time I had sex so vividly, I haven’t needed to experience it more than two or three times.  (Joke: I haven’t been that sexually inactive.)

That this is possible is, of course, preposterous.  But there’s something to it–some of us can daydream vastly more out of experiences than others, and thus get by happily on less first-hand experiences than others.  The natural theorist.  (And I have gotten along happily on a high daydream-to-reality ratio; my life has been unhappy for other reasons.  Or maybe for the related reason that I have almost never been able to daydream my way out of my many defects and failures sufficiently.)

.

AmazingCounters.com

Entry 1372 — My Psychology & Guilford’s

Saturday, February 15th, 2014

Today I’ll try to make sense about Guilford’s theory of intelligence versus mine.

Guilford’s Structure of Intellect

According to Guilford’s Structure of Intellect (SI) theory (1955), an individual’s performance on intelligence tests can be traced back to the underlying mental abilities or factors of intelligence. SI theory comprises up to 150 different intellectual abilities organized along three dimensions—Operations, Content, and Products.

My theory of cerebreffectiveness, which is more or less what Guilford’s “intellect” is, also posits numerous different intellectual abilities along with what might be called three dimensions: my charactration (unless I changed its name),  accommodance and accelerance.  Are they much like Guilford’s operations, content and products?  One way they definitely are not is that my three have a single mechanism over them which I consider the g factor (which he considered his theory to reject, although I don’t think it does).

It is a mechanism I call the “cerebrexecutive” which is responsible for supervising the interaction of the three cerebral dimensions responsible for all we think and do.  To describe the process simply, the cerebrexecutive oversees the flow of cerebral energy; that determines the way the three . . . “subcerebrexecutives” interact, which in turn determines which master-cells will be activated to produce the thoughts and behavior of the individual involved at that time.  Said master-cells contribute to many operations, perhaps the same ones  Guilford hypothesized, or ones similar to them.  They are the final determinants of cerebreffectiveness.

Note: I hope to get a decent name for my three operations.  Maybe “cerebreffectors.”  Or “cerebranisms.”

Eventually, I hope to provide detailed examples of thinking and behavior that will make all this much more clear than I suspect my previous paragraph does.

Operations dimension

SI includes six operations or general intellectual processes:

  1. Cognition – The ability to understand, comprehend, discover, and become aware of information.
  2. Memory recording – The ability to encode information.
  3. Memory retention – The ability to recall information.
  4. Divergent production – The ability to generate multiple solutions to a problem; creativity.
  5. Convergent production – The ability to deduce a single solution to a problem; rule-following or problem-solving.
  6. Evaluation – The ability to judge whether or not information is accurate, consistent, or valid.

Interesting.  It seems to me my theory treats cognition, memory recording and memory retention as a single process.  For me, sensory-cells are activated by stimuli in both the external and internal environments and, in turn activate master-cells (m-cells) in the cerebrum.  This activation the individual involved experiences as perceptual information.   At the same time, certain master-cells are activated whose activation the individual experiences as “retroceptual” information (or memories).  In other words, the individual becomes aware of a given moment’s information both from the immediate environments and recalled while data is recorded.

Note: I have no explanation for the individual’s consciousness of perceived and remember data.  That the individual exists with a consciousness that acts as I describe is the ground premise of my theory.  All I can say about it is that it exists.  (If it doesn’t exist, then I call what it does do as existing.)

At the same time that the individual becomes aware of what he perceives and remembers, he automatically forms a preliminary understanding, comprehension, discovery, idea, etc., of it.  Example: When little Willie sees a black cat, his nervous system activates m-cells whose activation he understands to mean “black cat.”  His nervous system also activates m-cells whose state he understands as “Max,” the name the actual cat reminds him is its.  We could call the three fused processes “cognition,” it seems to me.  Large forms of cognition, of course, occur; they simply take longer to do so, and include chains of moments rather than a single one.  Little Willie, watching his cat, connects it to the cockroach he saw scampering across the floor a moment ago (I’m drawing on my sad experience as an impoverished super-genius here–please send me some money) and may form an enlarged understanding of the situation.

Guilford’s other three operations are more complex.  Divergent production is what happens, according to my theory, when the cerebrexecutive puts the accommodance mechanism in charge of things.  What that does I will describe elsewhere.  Here, it suffices to say, it is the brain’s way of being creative.  (It causes the brain to become disorganized enough to form the novel linkages of data that creativity requires, to put it most simply.)

As for convergent production, that occurs, according to my theory, when the cerebrexecutive puts the charactration mechanism in charge (or, more exactly, leaves it in charge since it’s the cerebrum’s default boss).  This causes the narrowed concentration needed to follow a possible solution to a problem to its conclusion.  Accelerance will generally participate in both operations.  In divergence, it helps the brain pull quickly pull in a potential solution once recognized.  In convergence it strengthens and narrows the focus to defeat distraction until the solution is arrived at.

As for “evaluation,” I consider that a part of both divergent and convergent thinking.  If one’s cerebrexecutive is a good one, it will bring accelerance and accommodance into play in such a way as judge each attempted solution to a problem.

In short, it seems to me, that my theory contains all the operations Guilford’s does, although with much different mechanisms responsible for them–and, I suspect, with their nature, interactions and effects much more deeply worked out.

Content dimension

SI includes four broad areas of information to which the human intellect applies the six operations:

  1. Figural – Concrete, real world information, tangible objects — things in the environment. It includes visual: information perceived through seeing; auditory: information perceived through hearing; and kinesthetic: information perceived through one’s own physical actions.
  2. Symbolic – Information perceived as symbols or signs that stand for something else, e.g., Arabic numerals, the letters of an alphabet, or musical and scientific notations.
  3. Semantic – Concerned with verbal meaning and ideas. Generally considered to be abstract in nature.
  4. Behavioral – Information perceived as acts of people. (This dimension was not fully researched in Guilford’s project, remains theoretical, and is generally not included in the final model that he proposed for describing human intelligence.)

Guilford’s  “content” translates readily into my theory of awarenesses.  His “figural” is the same as the content of my fundaceptual awareness, which is where all our fundamental perceptions of our inner and outer environments are recorded as they occur or are remembered.  His “symbolic” content is the content of my reducticeptual awareness.  His semantic content is in this awareness, too–in the verboceptual subawareness of the reducticeptual awareness–since it is also symbolic.  It is, in fact, a dominant region of that awareness.  Guilford’s behavioral dimension is not researched at all in my project but is definitely part of it.  But it supplies the content of an awareness with much else in it, the anthroceptual awareness, which has to do with all human acts, our own as well as those of others, and the acts of all living creatures as well (and supernatural ones, too!)

My theory also has a behavraceptual awareness, but its function is to carry out our own behavior.  Like all the awarenesses, it interacts with other awarenesses, so contributes to the anthroceptual awareness to possibly help it do some of the things one’s behavioral dimension does.  My theory covers many more kinds of content than Guilford’s does, for it has, at last count, ten major awarenesses, most of them with many sub-awarenesses.  These I will introduce later.

Product dimension

As the name suggests, this dimension contains results of applying particular operations to specific contents. The SI model includes six products, in increasing complexity:

  1. Units – Single items of knowledge.
  2. Classes – Sets of units sharing common attributes.
  3. Relations – Units linked as opposites or in associations, sequences, or analogies.
  4. Systems – Multiple relations interrelated to comprise structures or networks.
  5. Transformations – Changes, perspectives, conversions, or mutations to knowledge.
  6. Implications – Predictions, inferences, consequences, or anticipations of knowledge.

Therefore, according to Guilford there are 5 x 3 x 6 = 90 intellectual abilities or factors (his research only confirmed about three behavioral abilities, so it is generally not included in the model). Each ability stands for a particular operation in a particular content area and results in a specific product, such as Comprehension of Figural Units or Evaluation of Semantic Implications.

I’m not entirely sure just how parallel my theory is to Guilford’s idea of products.  His units suggest my knowlecules, or units of data concerning one stimulus or stimulus cluster the individual takes as a unified whole (or not, depending on the context–e.g., a horse is such a unified whole, but so is a horse’s mane, or a herd of horses.  His classes are like what I call “knowleplexes”–for data more complicated than single units, like the entire field of zoology.  I consider his other products as simply different combinations of knowlecules.

I believe my theory contains elements his does not.  I’m thinking of mechanisms for determining cerebral pain and pleasure, which contribute greatly to cerebreffectiveness.  It’s what tags thoughts as errors or acts of a Grumman.  I mean, of genius.  Also the etiologiplex (or whatever I’m calling it) which is responsible for apprehending a thing’s cause or effect and recording it, which is obviously important cerebreffectively.  Ah, and there are many instincts in my theory such as fear of snakes, recognition of human faces, vicarious sympathy, etc., that could be considered products like Guilford’s.  A set of innate personae like Jung’s, too.

Guilford’s original model was composed of 120 components (when the behavioral component is included) because he had not separated Figural Content into separate Auditory and Visual contents, nor had he separated Memory into Memory Recording and Memory Retention. When he separated Figural into Auditory and Visual contents, his model increased to 5 x 5 x 6 = 150 categories. When Guilford separated the Memory functions, his model finally increased to 180 factors.

I suspect if I carried out the same calculation with my equivalents of Guilford’s operations, content and products, I’d get a lot more categories than 150.  I think I’d have at least one more set of factors, too–at the tail end of each sequence when muscles or glands turn a cerebreffect (i.e., the final result of a cerebrexecutive command) into an action (which isn’t always the case because many sequences end in thoughts or feeling only).  At this tail end, purely physical abilities convert the cerebreffective portion of the sequence into anthreffectiveness, the success of which can be due in great part to the effectiveness of the muscles’ or glands’ contribution.  But here my concern is only with Guilford’s idea of intelligence, or intellectual ability, and mine of cerebreffectiveness.

Criticism

Various researchers have criticized the statistical techniques used by Guilford. According to Jensen (1998), Guilford’s contention that a g-factor was untenable was influenced by his observation that cognitive tests of U.S. Air Force personnel did not show correlations significantly different from zero. According to one reanalysis, this resulted from artifacts and methodological errors. Applying more robust methodologies, the correlations in Guilford’s data sets are positive.  In another reanalysis, randomly generated models were found to be as well supported as Guilford’s own theory.

My criticism is merely that Guilford never had a chance to discuss his theory with me.  I think mine does what he was trying to do.  I doubt the application of statistics to his theory or competitors of it have much chance of being of value.  Too many variables concerned.

I’m pleased I got into Guilford.  His theory suggests to me that I’m not that much of a crank.  No doubt I’m finding it more like mine than it really is.  Still, I didn’t feel like I was straining too much to reveal the possible similarities I did.  Another plus of my adventure is that I think I learned a little more about what I’m doing.  Best of all, I had fun!  Zah-goo!

.

AmazingCounters.com

Entry 1371 — J. P. Guilford on Intelligence

Friday, February 14th, 2014

For around a week, I’ve been starting projects and quickly discovering that I’m in over my head.  At which point I try a different project with the same result.  What happens specifically is that I become aware that what I took to be a single topic had many subtopics–too many for me to organize.  For instance, my latest project is an essay on the IQ.  I thought it’d be easy because I’ve often written about it and thought I had an essay I could simply bring up to date.  Well, I had a very nice summary that I found in a long discussion of intelligence of mine from twenty or thirty years ago:

One more thing: by intelligence (or mental competence) I emphatically do not mean whatever it is that IQ tests measure.  Such tests are only concerned with conformity; speed and “correctness” on problems so trivial as to be almost the antithesis of the kind of problems live minds confront; mistakefree-ness (but so long as one can see & correct his mistakes, what real difference does it make how many he makes?); eagerness to win superficial acclaim; verbal, arithmetical and spatial “reasoning” (at the expense of athletic, musical, social and other forms of equally valid interplay with existence); and quantity of information (while disregarding the quality of one’s use of information which could permit a person with little information to organize it so well that he outperforms a walking encyclopedia).

But nothing else.  I was hoping for an essay of several thousand words.  I felt I could expand on the above but not for more than a thousand or so words.  I also realized there was quite a bit more to be said about the topic.  So I visited Wikipedia, and stole its entry on the Intelligence Quotient.  My thought was to use its data on the history of the IQ test, and maybe the nature/nurture debate.  But I found a number of relevant theories of intelligence, and studies of how IQ correlated with occupation, a little neurophysiology, and much else.  I had no idea how to proceed.

Whereas before when this happened, I just started a new project I hoped would be easier.  But it had become apparent that there weren’t any!  Brilliant solution: to grab something out of all the subjects having to do with IQ that I thought I could handle, and enjoy pontificating about and go with it, without worrying about how it would fit into any final essay about IQ that I might write.

At first I thought I might write about the g factor (theoretical general factor that is the basis of all intelligence).  That I soon found to be too much to chew on due to their being so many different ideas about it.  So I’ll first write about J. P. Guilford’s 3-part g factor (as I see it)–because I didn’t know anything about him or it, and found what Wikipedia said about fascinatingly close to my own ideas:

Guilford’s Structure of Intellect

According to Guilford’s Structure of Intellect (SI) theory (1955), an individual’s performance on intelligence tests can be traced back to the underlying mental abilities or factors of intelligence. SI theory comprises up to 150 different intellectual abilities organized along three dimensions—Operations, Content, and Products.

Operations dimension

SI includes six operations or general intellectual processes:

  1. Cognition – The ability to understand, comprehend, discover, and become aware of information.
  2. Memory recording – The ability to encode information.
  3. Memory retention – The ability to recall information.
  4. Divergent production – The ability to generate multiple solutions to a problem; creativity.
  5. Convergent production – The ability to deduce a single solution to a problem; rule-following or problem-solving.
  6. Evaluation – The ability to judge whether or not information is accurate, consistent, or valid.

Content dimension

SI includes four broad areas of information to which the human intellect applies the six operations:

  1. Figural – Concrete, real world information, tangible objects — things in the environment. It includes visual: information perceived through seeing; auditory: information perceived through hearing; and kinesthetic: information perceived through one’s own physical actions.
  2. Symbolic – Information perceived as symbols or signs that stand for something else, e.g., Arabic numerals, the letters of an alphabet, or musical and scientific notations.
  3. Semantic – Concerned with verbal meaning and ideas. Generally considered to be abstract in nature.
  4. Behavioral – Information perceived as acts of people. (This dimension was not fully researched in Guilford’s project, remains theoretical, and is generally not included in the final model that he proposed for describing human intelligence.)

Product dimension

As the name suggests, this dimension contains results of applying particular operations to specific contents. The SI model includes six products, in increasing complexity:

  1. Units – Single items of knowledge.
  2. Classes – Sets of units sharing common attributes.
  3. Relations – Units linked as opposites or in associations, sequences, or analogies.
  4. Systems – Multiple relations interrelated to comprise structures or networks.
  5. Transformations – Changes, perspectives, conversions, or mutations to knowledge.
  6. Implications – Predictions, inferences, consequences, or anticipations of knowledge.

Therefore, according to Guilford there are 5 x 3 x 6 = 90 intellectual abilities or factors (his research only confirmed about three behavioral abilities, so it is generally not included in the model). Each ability stands for a particular operation in a particular content area and results in a specific product, such as Comprehension of Figural Units or Evaluation of Semantic Implications.

Guilford’s original model was composed of 120 components (when the behavioral component is included) because he had not separated Figural Content into separate Auditory and Visual contents, nor had he separated Memory into Memory Recording and Memory Retention. When he separated Figural into Auditory and Visual contents, his model increased to 5 x 5 x 6 = 150 categories. When Guilford separated the Memory functions, his model finally increased to 180 factors.

Criticism

Various researchers have criticized the statistical techniques used by Guilford. According to Jensen (1998), Guilford’s contention that a g-factor was untenable was influenced by his observation that cognitive tests of U.S. Air Force personnel did not show correlations significantly different from zero. According to one reanalysis, this resulted from artifacts and methodological errors. Applying more robust methodologies, the correlations in Guilford’s data sets are positive.  In another reanalysis, randomly generated models were found to be as well supported as Guilford’s own theory.

I hope to post a discussion of Guilford’s structure in my entry for tomorrow, comparing and contrasting it to my own theory.  The latter, I think, has mechanisms that may repair what I think is wrong with Guilford’s.  It is also much simpler . . . well, perhaps not simpler, but having fewer elements.

.

AmazingCounters.com

Entry 1328 — My Stupidest Idea?

Thursday, January 2nd, 2014

About a month ago I had an idea so stupid I never wrote it down.  But somehow I more than half believe in it!  In any case, it may be entertaining, and I need something for today, so here it is: when we struggle to answer some problem and fail, our brain will eventually connect it to–here’s my idea–a False Solution.  Here’s what makes it wacko: we know it’s false but accept it as our solution, anyway!  And it explains nothing, it just says to you, you got it without telling you why.

Here’s what I tentatively think happens: a mechanism recognizing great puzzlement sticks this false solution to our thinking about the problem, with it clearly labeled “crap”; but the mechanism also lowers the pain that failed solutions generally cause, and which make us keep struggling with the problems causing them.  So we accept it.  It keeps us from ever solving the problem BUT makes up for that by keeping us from wasting too much time and energy trying to solve a problem we can’t solve, because we’re too inept, or have no likelihood of acquiring sufficient data to solve it, or it’s unsolvable (e.g., why iz we here).

To cast a better light on it, I could call it the Unsolvability Urceptual Knowlecule (UUK).  A form of x is x because.

The alert amongst you may well see how such a thing may just explain . . . You-Know-Who, Almighty.  In fact, I think certain things some find animistic vague answers to may connect to the UUK, which strengthens and personifies them.  In other words, if it exists, it would be the basis of a human instinct to form and believe in religions.  Always in tension with the instinct to be rational, even–I suspect–for the most devout.  And, in reverse, for the least devout.
.

Entry 1299 — The Two Human Consciousnesses

Saturday, December 14th, 2013

My latest Important Discovery about the Human Intelligence is that each of us has two consciousnesses, or one with two departments: the cerebral consciousness and the cerebellar consciousness.  We each also has two kinds of intuition.  One is an understanding that feels right but has not yet been validated by reason due to lack of full confirmation by data.  The other is an understanding so strongly confirmed by data that it has become “unconscious.”  I put the latter in quotation marks, because a person acting on it is consciously aware of it, but only in his cerebellar consciousness.  That means he is not verbalizing it, among other things, one of which is that he is using it so smoothly and effortlessly that he doesn’t hold it in mind long enough to be more than momentarily aware of it.  He has automatized it.

It will not lead to creativity but make creativity easier.  Cerebral intuition is the kind of understanding that leads to creativity.  Warning: the creativity it leads to may be defective, seriously defective.  Indeed, it will lead to error (which is why it’s an important part of my poem of yesterday’s entry), error which reason must evaluate before it can be considered worthwhile creativity, preferably one’s own reason, but often someone else’s, and eventually the world-as-a-whole’s.  Which is fine, too.

When one is in what some psychologists refer to as “flow,” one’s brain pretty much shuts down one’s cerebral consciousness, but one is still conscious!  A minor terminological point, perhaps not even worth mentioning, since calling the cerebellar consciousness “the unconsciousness” works more than adequately.  But it is incorrect, I’m strongly convinced.  The true unconscious mind, in knowlecular psychology, is simply the brain’s collection of mnemoducts that, I claim, hold all our memories.  Are retroceptual warehouse.  It doesn’t do anything.

I contend that one is always aware, at least while it is going on, of one’s creativity-in-progress, although rarely aware of it as that.  In dreams, for instance, pivotal connections are being creatively made that one is briefly aware of without having any idea of them as contributing toward the creative solution, or attempted solution, of a problem important to one.    Intellectual creativity of all kinds is carried out by the cerebral consciousness in many ways that I have covered in my writings but lack time to cover at this time here.

.

Entry 1176 — Natural and Learned Concepts

Thursday, August 8th, 2013

A few days ago while discussing conceptual poetry, which seems to be attracting a lot of attention amongst poetry people, I got mired in confusion: I realized I didn’t know what I was taking about.  This morning  (no, yesterday morning since I’m writing this a day in advance) I suddenly felt I did, so wrote the following to New-Poetry:

I think I’ve solved my question about what Grumman was trying to put into words.  It is that there are two kinds of concepts, those we perceive “naturally” the way we perceive the color red, and those we learn, which are more complex and ordinarily the only mental objects considered to be concepts (so far as I know).  I realized this while thinking about numbers.  The number one is a natural concept, I claim, because–I claim–one perceives a thing’s “oneness”  the same way one perceives a thing’s redness.  Thinking about it further, I decided that what we experience (due to a simple innate brain counting mechanism) is “absence of duplication.”  The mechanism consists of a storage chamber holding everything a person has seen (I’m considering the visual only for simplicity’s sake) over the past minute or so; and matching chamber with a slot for the object being tested for “oneness” and a slot into which each of the things in the storage chamber are inserted.  The matching chamber has a second compartment where one image overlaps the other and differences and samenesses are counted and a percentage arrived at that indicates match or non-match.

If nothing matches, the object being tested gets a one.  One match gives it a two.  Beyond that, who knows, but I’m sure four or five matches give the object a many.  Words labeling each of these, like “one,” “alone,” “unique,” “twin,” etc.  Larger numbers are learned.  Five dots gets a many from the counting mechanism–but eventually is learned as a hand of fingers or the like, which is reduced to the word, “five.”

I believe more complex mathematical mechanisms may have evolved, but haven’t thought any out.  I can’t believe I’m saying anything very wrong or new.  But I work from introversion almost entirely–being too lazy for research and related work.

So, to get to POETRY, I suppose it doesn’t matter whether a conceptual poem’s concept/s is/are natural or learned.  But I think all concepts are natural at the core.

Boy, I wish I were 25–and able to focus on ONE area of investigation the way Darwin did!  This would be a good such area to spend a life on.

Note: in knowlecular psychology, natural concepts are termed “urceptual concepts.”
.

Entry 1124 — Neologizania « POETICKS

Entry 1124 — Neologizania

Late Sunday.  I must be out of the null zone because I’ve been neologizing like mad lately.  One of my new terms is “ellipsistry” for ellipsis poetry.  No, this is not going into my Serious Taxonomy, but the way Marton is going, and the fact that others have made ellipsis poems has me close to thinking such poetry should have a special name.  Serious new Grummanisms are “triumphantry,” “moralitry,” “conspiraplex” . . .   Hmmm, not as many as I thought.  But there was “unseveraling,” too.  I don’t count my ad hoc poeticisms as full-scale coinages, though–just my Important Verosophical Terms.  “Neologizania” is an ad hoc joke, so doesn’t count, either.  “Triumphantry,” which is the feeling of success one experiences when achieving a victory, may be a term I’ve re-coined.  Ditto the other two, now that I think about it.  “Moralitry” is what I call telling other human beings how to live their lives.  I consider it one of the major human endeavers along with art, verosophy, survival, etc.  “Conspiraplex” represents “insane conspiracy theory” as opposed to a conspiracy theory that makes sense: the theory that Bush and Cheney master-minded the destruction of the twin towers, for instance.  I can’t think of a conspiracy theory, by my definition, that makes sense, but there must be some.

Monday.  Here’s another coinage: “ethicry.”  The attempt to live morally.  Opposed to ethics, which is the attempt to determine what living morally is.

Hmmm, not for the first time I find I’ve made up a word I already had another word for–at least in part.  Only six months ago I coined “dominantry” for “what politicans and warriors of various .rts do to achieve positions of power which allow them to tell others how to live theirs lives.  That would include what I mean by “moralitry.”  Still, the latter covers what politicians do, and . . . “subjugatry” would work for what warriors do.  I think “ethicry” a good addition to my list of final human activities, which gives me eight: Art, Verosophy, Utilitry, Recreation, Sustenation, Quotidiation, Ethicry and Dominantry (in order of their importance . . . to me, that is.

.

Leave a Reply